为了正常的体验网站,请在浏览器设置里面开启Javascript功能!

法律理论与价值判断

2011-01-14 31页 pdf 134KB 14阅读

用户头像

is_193419

暂无简介

举报
法律理论与价值判断 VITTORIO VILLA LEGAL THEORY AND VALUE JUDGMENTS� ABSTRACT. The aim of the paper is that of putting into question the dichotomy between fact-judgments and value judgments in the legal domain, with its epis- temological presuppositions (descriptivist image of knowl...
法律理论与价值判断
VITTORIO VILLA LEGAL THEORY AND VALUE JUDGMENTS� ABSTRACT. The aim of the paper is that of putting into question the dichotomy between fact-judgments and value judgments in the legal domain, with its epis- temological presuppositions (descriptivist image of knowledge) and its method- ological implications for legal knowledge (value freedom principle and neutrality thesis). The basic question that I will try to answer is whether and on what condi- tions strong ethical value-judgments belong within legal knowledge. I criticize the traditional positivist positions that have fully accepted the value- freedom principle and value-neutrality thesis, but I also submit to critical scrutiny the new post-positivist views, that, even if they show interesting conceptual developments on the matter, end up, nevertheless, by presupposing the same epistemological image, which I call descriptivism. I stress that only by giving up descriptivism and accepting constructivism as a general image of knowledge is it possible to see the problem of value-ladenness of legal knowledge in a new light. On the basis of the constructivist image, I present two theses: firstly, at a much broader epistemological level, I advance the minimalist thesis on value- judgments, which simply removes the general ban on treating values as present within knowledge; secondly, I advance the strong thesis on legal value-judgments, which consists in arguing for the necessary presence of ethical value-judgments in legal knowledge. I draw, in the end, some important implications from acceptance of the strong thesis. One of these implications is a new distinction that replaces the traditional distinction between fact-judgments and value judgments, namely, the distinction between value-judgments exhibiting a cognitive function and value- judgments exhibiting a creative function. KEY WORDS: value-judgments, legal knowledge, descriptivism value freedom principle, constructivism � I wrote this paper during a period of research spent in the Centre for Law and Society, Edinburgh University, thanks to an invitation by Zenon Bankowski and Neil MacCormick, supported by the Lindsay Bequest in the Faculty of Law of Edinburgh University. I would like to thank the Faculty most warmly for this support, and also to thank very much my friend Neil MacCormick both for the great help that he gave me in linguistic improvements to my first draft, and for having read previous versions of the paper giving valuable advice and criticism. Law and Philosophy 16: 447–477, 1997. c 1997 Kluwer Academic Publishers. Printed in the Netherlands. 448 VITTORIO VILLA 1. INTRODUCTION It has always been an influential and widely shared idea, in the research program of legal positivism,1 that there is a sort of dichoto- mous opposition between two kinds of discourses about positive law: the first one is ‘descriptive’ in character, because its aim is informa- tive: it tries, as a matter of fact, to give either theoretical explanations of certain general features of positive law (from the point of view of legal theory), or semantical reconstructions of some specific part of a given legal system (from the point of view of legal dogmatics); the second one is ‘evaluative’ in character, because it expresses, albeit in different ways, some sort of attitudes or commitments, ethical, political, ideological, or the like, on the given object.2 This opposition is by no means a necessary feature of legal posi- tivism; yet, if it is accepted, a more specific methodological thesis can 1 In my opinion the notion of legal positivism has a much broader scope than what is currently assumed, because it includes all the conceptions that presuppose a certain concept of positive law, a concept according to which: i) law is always and integrally an human product; ii) this product is radically contingent, in the sense that its connection with morals, which could even be considered as ‘necessary’ for certain legal systems (this is the case of our current western legal systems) regards values that are always context-bound, that is, values which can never be objectively justified. From this point of view, there is a mutually exclusive opposition between natural law and legal positivism (opposition which amounts to an opposition between ethical objectivism and ethical relativism): both could be defined putting the sign of negation before the opposite one (positivist or naturalist). It is important to remark that, according to this definition, even legal realism (and Dworkin’s theory) is a form of positivism. For this kind of definition of legal positivism, see my book Conoscenza giuridica e concetto di diritto positivo. Lezioni di filosofia del diritto (Torino: Giappichelli, 1993), pp. 105–108. 2 A classical formulation of this thesis is given by Kelsen: according to Kelsen, legal science’s function does not consist in attributing values or in expressing evaluations, but rather, in a description of its own object, description which is performed leaving values out of consideration. See H. Kelsen, Reine Rechtslehre, Italian. transl. (Torino: Einaudi, 1975 (3rd edn)), p. 84. According to another leading figure in legal positivism, Hart, the separation, internal to the domain of discourses referring to positive law, between conceptual analyses and evaluations, represents one of the five meanings usually given to the notion of legal positivism. See H.L.A. Hart, ‘Positivism and the Separation of Law and Morals’, Harvard Law Review I (1958), pp. 593 ff. A very influential statement of this thesis, in Italian analytical positivism, is that given by Bobbio. According to Bobbio, compliance with the value-freedom principle constitutes one of legal positivism’s three aspects. See N. Bobbio, Giusnaturalismo e positivismo giuridico (Milano: Ed. di Comunita´, 1972), pp. 105–107. LEGAL THEORY AND VALUE JUDGMENTS 449 be derived from it: the thesis according to which it is at least possible, if not highly recommended, for legal theorists and jurists, to produce purely descriptive discourses on positive law, that is discourses from which every kind of value-judgment or of commitment, whether political, ethical, or the like, is radically excluded. This thesis can be – and is in fact – held by positivists independently of the different ways in which these descriptive discourses might be characterized (for instance, as scientific discourses, in a strong or in a weak sense,3 etc.). Hereinafter, this thesis will be called the ‘neutrality thesis’.4 It does not matter, for the tasks of this paper, to take into account the different ways in which this thesis might be coordinated with – or sometimes logically deduced from – other theses. In my opinion, this thesis has anyway gained a quite canonical formulation, in con- temporary legal positivism, in so far as it has represented one of the ways of stating the separability thesis (its methodological version) and has become, according to prescriptivist positions in analytical legal philosophy, one of the (arguably logical) outcomes of the great division5 in the legal domain. In the space of this paper, however, I will not deal with these quite complicated matters, because I think in any event that the neutrality thesis can be analysed in its pure form, that is, through examin- ing its proper epistemological and methodological justifications and leaving out of consideration its possible logical or conceptual con- nections. This thesis, in short, can stand on its own feet, as far as it can be conceived as the legal version of the highly influential and historically long-enduring methodological principle usually called the principle of ‘value-freedom’, in its connection with the episte- mological foundation given to it by empiricist images of science. Seen in its pure form, therefore, the neutrality thesis incorporates, as its basic epistemological foundation, the traditional empiricist 3 I have studied the problem of the scientific character of legal theorists’ and jurists’ discourses in my book Teorie delle scienze naturali e teorie della scienza giuridica. Modelli e analogie (Milano: Giuffre´, 1984). 4 I borrow this expression from K. Fu¨sser, ‘Farewell to ‘Legal Positivism’: the Separation Thesis Unravelling’, in R.P. George (ed.) The Autonomy of Law: Essays on Legal Positivism (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1996), pp. 119–62. 5 See on this point Celano, who thinks that to accept the ‘great division’ logically implies refusing any place for value-judgments inside social sciences. See B. Celano, Dialettica della giustificazione pratica. Saggio sulla legge di Hume (Torino: Giappichelli, 1994), p. 49. 450 VITTORIO VILLA opposition between fact-judgments and value-judgments, and, as its methodological corollary, that set of rules which go under the head- ing of the value-freedom principle. This will be the version of the thesis that I will put under critical scrutiny in this paper. Those who side with the neutrality thesis are ready to acknowl- edge, of course, that descriptions and evaluations can easily occur together in the practices of theorists and – more often – of jurists; but they stress, nevertheless, that it is just one of the most significant goals of legal philosophy to dispel this practical (perhaps unavoid- able) inconsistency, establishing, with the maximum of clarity and exactness, the proper conceptual boundaries between the two domains. It is important to note that, in this kind of perspective, legal value- judgments are almost always equated with judgments expressing a – positive or negative – stance on a given legal system, as a whole or in one of its parts: in other words, according to this opinion, to give a value-judgment implies almost always to take a stance from the inside of the system, to express a practical attitude towards it.6 I am of the opinion that this is a big misunderstanding which it is important to dispel; and I will try to do so in the paper. The neutrality thesis presupposes, as can be easily shown, the methodological monism that is so typical of neopositivism (‘the same method, that of natural sciences, must be applied to all scien- tific or quasi-scientific disciplines’). But it cannot be ignored that the legal domain is, in some aspects, profoundly different from that of the natural sciences; in the legal domain, to take an example that touches directly our point of interest, it could happen (and certainly it happens today, in western legal systems) that ethical values penetrate deeply ‘inside the law’ and so become part of the object of study, through the intervention of the legislator (as contents of explicitly issued legal principles), or of legal doctrine (as implicit legal principles recon- structed by jurists), or, in the end, of the loyalist lay members of the given legal community (who express their value-laden acceptance of the system). But this situation doesn’t necessarily pose a threat 6 This kind of conviction is expressed very clearly by Ross, when he says that the ‘descriptive terminology’ that is used in the doctrinal study of law “has nothing to do with moral approval or condemnation” of a given legal system’s rules. See A. Ross, On Law and Justice (London: Stevens & Sons Limited, 1958), pp. 31–32. LEGAL THEORY AND VALUE JUDGMENTS 451 for the neutrality thesis: here the methodological rule to be followed by jurists should be, according to Bobbio:7 to treat these values and value-judgments ‘as if they were facts’, with the same neutral atti- tude as that supposedly adopted by scientists towards facts. And this is considered by traditional legal positivism a viable strategy in the legal domain, as far as jurists succeed in limiting themselves to con- centrating their attention on the social and empirically accountable sources through which these values and evaluations become part of positive law or contribute to its effectiveness. If we enlarge for a while the scope of the analysis, inserting this thesis into the much broader context of the most general prob- lems faced by legal theories, we can soon notice that the dichotomy between fact-judgments and value-judgments does not stand alone, in complete isolation; on the contrary, it is strictly connected (through logical and conceptual relations) with other dichotomies, form- ing a sort of an ‘interactive net’. These dichotomies refer to all the spectrum of legal practices performed by theorists, jurists and public officials (judges, above all), and divide invariably these practices into two opposite classes, marked by contrasting labels such as ‘interpreting existing law’ and ‘creating new law’ (in legal interpretation), ‘describing law as it is’ and ‘prescribing law as it should be’, ‘making discourses upon law’ (and so using interpretive arguments) and ‘making discourses inside law’ (and so using produc- tive arguments8). In all these dichotomies it is more or less presup- posed that legal practices can be distinguished with the help of two opposed qualifications, ‘objective’ and ‘subjective’, both interpreted in a strong sense. From this point of view, all the descriptive dis- courses have to be qualified as ‘objective’, and all the value-laden discourses have to be qualified as ‘subjective’. It is worth noting, by the way, that this kind of demarcationism produces the undesir- able outcome of putting all the value-judgments (from ‘reports of taste’ to ‘ethical judgments’) into the same class, characterized by the possession of these supposedly subjective features. 7 N. Bobbio, Giusnaturalismo e positivismo giuridico (supra n. 2), pp. 125–26. 8 This distinction is drawn by R. Guastini, ‘Produzione di norme a mezzo di norme’, in Etica e diritto, ed. by L. Gianformaggio and E. Lecaldano (Bari: Laterza, 1986), pp. 175, 186–87. I have criticized this distinction in my ‘Legal Analogy Between Interpretive Arguments and Productive Arguments’, in Legal Knowledge and Analogy, ed. by P. Nerhot (Dordrecht: Kluwer, 1991), pp. 165–82. 452 VITTORIO VILLA One of the claims that I will make in the paper is that this demar- cation is not only epistemologically flawed, but that it also produces unsatisfactory outcomes at political and practical levels. It goes with- out saying that Dworkin is obviously a good ally in the battle against this highly influential conceptual framework, even if he is not, unfor- tunately, sufficiently clear and analytically rigorous in developing his ideas, given that among other things he leaves the epistemological and semantical presuppositions of many of his ideas too obscure.9 But it is better to go on in an orderly way, and to mention, before all, the most general claims advanced in the paper. First, I will make some epistemological claims that represent a criticism of the general presuppositions of the neutrality thesis, and I will proceed to suggest a provisional statement of a new perspective on the matter. What I will try to show is, in particular, that the neutral- ity thesis invariably presupposes a very influential and historically long-enduring epistemological position, that I have already called, in other works of mine, ‘descriptivism’,10 using an expression which has close connections with Putnam’s ‘metaphysical realism’.11 It is interesting to note that this position, which will be examined in due course, is still taken for granted by most of the contemporary positivistic legal theories, even if its implications for legal practice are put into question by some of these theories. For example, even when legal realists reject the supposedly objective elements of legal discourses (rejecting, for instance, the idea that interpretation is to be regarded as a semantical discovery of the meaning of rules), their own approach is still dependent on that presupposed episte- mological position. These skeptical theories, that is, do still rely on this epistemological presupposition; what changes is only the legal philosophers’ opinion about the applicability of this epistemological 9 Dworkin, anyway, points outs very clearly the need for sharply distinguishing ‘ethical claims’ and ‘mere reports of taste’ in legal domain. See R. Dworkin, Law’s Empire (London: Fontana Press, 1986), p. 81. For a much broader distinction, epis- temologically grounded, between objective and subjective value-judgments, see H. Putnam, Reason, Truth and History (Cambridge Mass.: Cambridge University Press, 1981), p. 156. 10 See again my book Conoscenza giuridica e concetto di diritto positivo (supra n. 1), pp. 173–85. 11 Putnam exposes and criticizes this epistemological conception in many places; but see particularly H. Putnam, Reason, Truth and History (supra n. 9), pp. 49–50. LEGAL THEORY AND VALUE JUDGMENTS 453 framework as an interpretive scheme for understanding legal prac- tices. From this point of view, therefore, it is a workable hypothesis to assume that legal skepticism, in most of its versions, is parasitic on legal objectivism: with the difference that legal skepticism thinks that objectivism is no longer a live option in the legal domain. It is important to add, nevertheless, that this situation has quite dramatically changed in recent years. Analytical legal positivism has tried very hard, in this more recent period, to put into question one or the other of these dichotomies.12 Here the solutions to be advanced cannot be, of course, those of ceasing to draw distinctions among different aspects of legal practices, but, rather, those of making them more adequate, using more sophisticated tools (in my opinion we should adopt, first of all, a different image of knowledge). Anyway, the broad discussion on the sources and flaws of these dichotomies cannot be the concern of this paper. Neither can the general epistemological framework be put in question as the main issue of the paper. It has been a main topic of previous work, and I am currently re-engaging with it as a long-term research program.13 Coming back again to the changes occurring in contemporary analyt- ical legal philosophy, perhaps it is worth anticipating what I will say in a more detailed way later on: these changes of opinion, or at least these new ways of approaching the matter of legal value-judgments, do not succeed, in most cases, in avoiding confusions, inadequacies and misunderstandings. In this broader context, the more modest task of the paper is that of making some observations, of epistemological and methodological character, on the supposed opposition between descriptive or infor- mative legal discourses on one side, and evaluative discourses on the 12 In recent years, for instance, there has developed a very interesting debate on which is the most feasible way to work out a concept of objectivity for legal prac- tices that could represent a viable alternative to both strong objectivist positions, too much compromised with metaphysical realism, and subjectivist positions, which share relativistic or conventionalist premises. Among these attempts, see particularly J. Coleman & B. Leiter, ‘Determinacy, Objectivity, and Authority’, in Law and Interpretation: Essays in Legal Philosophy, ed. by A. Marmor (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1995), pp. 203–78, and N. Stavropoulos, Objectivity in Law (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1996). 13 I can only make reference here to my recent book Conoscenza giuridica e concetto di diritto positivo (supra n. 1) and to my new book Costruttivismo e teorie del diritto (Torino: Giappichelli), which will be published later in this year. 454 VITTORIO VILLA other side. For brevity’s sake I will assume, without discussion, that these descriptive discourses can be considered as instances of what may be suitably called ‘legal knowledge’. The centre of our concern in the paper will therefore be that of the relationship between legal knowledge and value-judgments. I have said before that traditional legal positivism conceives this relationship as a radical opposition.
/
本文档为【法律理论与价值判断】,请使用软件OFFICE或WPS软件打开。作品中的文字与图均可以修改和编辑, 图片更改请在作品中右键图片并更换,文字修改请直接点击文字进行修改,也可以新增和删除文档中的内容。
[版权声明] 本站所有资料为用户分享产生,若发现您的权利被侵害,请联系客服邮件isharekefu@iask.cn,我们尽快处理。 本作品所展示的图片、画像、字体、音乐的版权可能需版权方额外授权,请谨慎使用。 网站提供的党政主题相关内容(国旗、国徽、党徽..)目的在于配合国家政策宣传,仅限个人学习分享使用,禁止用于任何广告和商用目的。

历史搜索

    清空历史搜索